Lapas attēli
PDF
ePub

Mr. GOLDSTEIN. I was struck that what I thought I was hearing the first panel talk about was the question of moral right. Yet, until I saw the presentation of John Huston on the screen, I didn't hear that phrase used. I don't know if they were studiously staying away from it, or if it was just overlooked. But, to the extent that I can give legal content to the testimony of the first panel, it seems that they are talking to some degree about the continental doctrine of moral right.

I would say, in direct response to your question, that I think it would be wonderful if we began to look at the legal models offered by other countries in responding to many of the same problems that we have here. If anything, copyright policymakers in this country are too xenophobic. We have looked to the United States for the exclusive wisdom of solutions. I would caution, however, on two points.

First, it is common to think of moral right as a unified concept. In fact, it is a multifaceted and a multifarious concept. Moral right is multifaceted in the sense that it covers not only the right against distortion, but in some places a right of withdrawal as well as other rights. It is multifarious in the sense that, although several nations adopt the moral right, none has exactly the same body of law as the other. We must attend carefully, then, to what it is we are talking about when we speak of moral right and recognize as well that we ought not just look at the laws on the books.

German law, for example, might give you the impression that the right against distortion is, in fact, inalienable-that it cannot be waived and that directors could not waive it even if they wanted to. In fact and in practice, as it works out, it is almost fully, if not fully, waivable.

The other caution I would urge is, if we begin looking abroad for moral right models, we recognize the cultural and political differences that separate many of those nations from the United States.

There is a strong cultural tendency in the civil law tradition to honor authors' rights-a tendency that doesn't exist in the United States. It has cultural roots. To the extent that we want to adopt that, it is a noble object, to be sure, but there may be countervailing considerations, one of them being the principle of freedom of contract which has its own cultural content in this country.

The other caution I would add is that the political systems of other countries differ dramatically from ours in one very important respect. The national government, which has enacted the relevant laws on moral right in France, Germany, and Italy, is a thoroughly centralized government. It is the principal lawmaker in those countries. By contrast, in the United States, with our Federal system, important powers are left to the States. Traditionally, interests in reputation—the interests protected by the law of privacy, publicity, defamation-torts have been the preserve of the States. This would be a notable intrusion, I might add, of the Federal Government into what has traditionally been a State concern.

I am not saying it should preclude that step, but it is another caution that might be considered.

Senator LEAHY. Most of the moral rights clauses have really grown up out of court cases. Invasion of privacy is a definition.

Mr. GOLDSTEIN. Exactly.

[ocr errors]

Senator LEAHY. I am going to back up and ask you, am I correct that there is no clear-cut line of court cases that would be applicable to the questions we have heard here today?

Mr. GOLDSTEIN. Well, again, if you are dealing with a case where there is no contract, and it is a public domain work, there is little case law.

Actually, one of the most powerful bodies of case laws supporting this approach is Federal case law under section 43(a) of the Lanham Act.

Senator LEAHY. If we wanted to make clear law in this area of moral rights, we have to write the law anew?

Mr. GOLDSTEIN. That is correct, if one wanted to do that.

Senator LEAHY. If one wanted. I realize that becomes a political question as well as a legal question, of course.

Mr. GOLDSTEIN. It is also a resources question. Do you want to rely on a system that has lots of holes in it but does incrementally protect authors' rights, or do you want to spend the time and place that high on your agenda?

Senator LEAHY. I think you stated the issue very well, Professor. I appreciate it.

Again, I appreciate your taking the time to come here. And once you have received your copy of your testimony back, if there is something additional you want to add, don't hesitate to do so. Let me know and we will make it part of the record because I think more and more, as we look back at this question, that you are going to be seen as the wrap-up hitter. It is your testimony we are going to be looking to.

Mr. GOLDSTEIN. Thank you very much.

Senator LEAHY. We will stand in recess subject to the call of the Chair.

[Whereupon, at 12:20 p.m., the subcommittee adjourned, subject to the call of the Chair.]

[merged small][merged small][ocr errors][merged small][merged small][merged small][merged small][merged small][merged small][merged small][merged small][merged small][merged small][merged small]
[ocr errors]

am Associate Professor of Law at George Mason University.

I am pleased

to be able to submit this testimony for inclusion in the hearings of the

Subcommittee on the color ization of black and white motion pictures.

The

views that I am about to express are my own.

I am not acting as advocate

for any group.

I am delighted that the Subcommittee has moved so promptly to informi

itself and to attempt to identity and prioritize the issues

in the

color ization controversy.

As I see it, the central issue is artistic

integrity.

I do not oppose colorization because I think that modern

viewer's need a cultural uplift; I oppose it because the motion picture

that they will

see will not be the motion picture as it was made.

The claim that color ization widens the audience for classic black and

white motion pictures is spurious for the simple reason that viewers will not be seeing those motion pictures at all; rather, they will be seeing distortions of them in colors suggestive of a 1939 World's Fair postcard. (This fact produces a curious dilemma for the colorizers: hand, they must argue that colorizing results in more people seeing the

on the one

or aginal -an

argument that tends to minimize the effect of color ization on

the original; on the other hand, they must argue that the colorized

ver sion is sufficiently different from the original to consitute a derivative work--an argument that weakens their claim that they are

widening the audience for the original.)

I believe that the authors of motion pictures--as all authors--have

the right to have their work presented to the public in the form in which

it was created.

At a time when the United States is consider ing adherence

to the Berne Convention with its clear moral rights provision (Article byis) and at a time when five states have moved in the direction of

insuring artistic integrity,

it would be anomalous for Congress to withold

legal

protection for the integrity of black and white motion pictures.

Legal protection of artistic integrity, however, is not a matter of

accepting a foreign concept.

Even our current copyright law--which I

admit is primarily aimed at economic rights--recognizes the non-economic

[ocr errors][merged small][merged small]

for example, recently reiterated that the personal values of privacy and

creative control

were implicit in the sec. 106(3) right of first Hareer___Row_Publishers_v. Nation Entererises, 105 S.Ct.

publication.

2218, 2228 (1985).

As far back as 1976 the U.S. Court of Appeals for the

Second Circuit held that a cause of action to protect artistic integrity was implicit in copyright law. Gilliam_y._American Broadcasting_Cos., 538

F.2d 14, 24 (1976).

(That case involved a broadcast of a Monty Python

television program.

It should be noted that the "mutilation" identified

by the court was the showing of the program--the original versions of the

program were unaffected by the defendants' actions.)

The Copyright Act of

1976 even contains an express provision protective of artistic integrity.

Sec. 115, which deals with compulsory licenses for making and distributing

phonorecords, provides that "the arrangement shall not change the basic

[blocks in formation]

derivative works and for artistic integrity through the concept of droit.

moral

(mor al rights! is evidence of the fact that there is no inherent

!

theor etical problem. Francon, Proeriete_Litteraire_et_Artistique, 52-53 (1970). Moreover, the requirement of originality in our own Copyright Act

indicates a distinction between mere distortions and bona fide derivative

works.

Indeed, the late Professor Nimmer when writing in his famous

treatise on copyright law about the issue of preemption of the artistic

integrity provisions of the California Art Preservation Act supported a

distinction between mutilation and defacement on the one hand and true

der a vative works on the other.

Sec. 8.210D), text accompanying nn.

34.23-. 30 (1986).

The distinction is admittedly a fine one, but surely no less

evanescent than the concept of originality itself.

Compare, for exampie,

the reasoning in Alva_Studios_v. _Winninger, 177 F. Supp. 265 (S.D.N.Y. 1959), where a scale reduction of Rodin's sculpture, "Hand of God," was

[ocr errors][merged small]

F.2d 486 (2d Cir. 1976), where a plastic model of a cast iron "Uncle Sam"

bank was held not to be sufficiently original.

When Congress and the

courts are convinced that a value should have legal protection, imprecise

distinctions have proved workable.

Common law copyright is another indication that the personal

dimension

of the creative process has been recognized in American law.

Warren and

Brandeis, for example, relied on the privacy protection aspect of the

common law right of first publication in their famous article to prove

that the value of privacy had been given legal recognition in American

law.

"The Right of Privacy," 4 Harv. L. Rev. 193 (1890).

The fact that

conmon law copyright has largely been preempted by the 1976 Copyright Act

does not neqate the point that American law has been appreciative of the nori-economic aspects of copyright, one of which is artistic integrity.

Indeed, the U.S. Supreme Court in Harper &_fow drew on the per sonal aspect

of the common law right of first publication in arriving at its decision

regarding sec.

106(3) of the current Act.

Supra at 2226-27.

Thus far

I have tried to prove that there is ample evidence in

American copyright law, both common and statutory, of the recognition of

per soral values, such as artistic integrity.

Although this recognition is

emerging more and more out of the background of copyright law through

cases such as Harper_&_Row and through awareness of the structure of

copyright law in other countries, such as the adherents of Berne,

feder al

legislation is necessary not only to fix the concept firmly in the

American legal consciousness, but also to deal with the more pressing,

concrete violations of the personal rights of authors such as the

infringement of the artistic integrity of black and white motion pictures

through color ization.

The law of contract interpretation and the Federal Trademark Act are

not adequate to insure the artistic integrity of motion pictures.

What I

have said regarding moral rights in general in my comment on the report of

« iepriekšējāTurpināt »